Nagarjuna,
Shunyata and Anatman
Dr.
Amartya Kumar Bhattacharya
BCE
(Hons.) ( Jadavpur ), MTech ( Civil ) ( IIT Kharagpur ), PhD ( Civil
) ( IIT Kharagpur ), Cert.MTERM ( AIT Bangkok ), CEng(I), FIE,
FACCE(I), FISH, FIWRS, FIPHE, FIAH, FAE, MIGS, MIGS – Kolkata
Chapter, MIGS – Chennai Chapter, MISTE, MAHI, MISCA, MIAHS, MISTAM,
MNSFMFP, MIIBE, MICI, MIEES, MCITP, MISRS, MISRMTT, MAGGS, MCSI,
MIAENG, MMBSI, MBMSM
Chairman
and Managing Director,
MultiSpectra
Consultants,
23,
Biplabi Ambika Chakraborty Sarani,
Kolkata
– 700029, West Bengal, INDIA.
E-mail:
dramartyakumar@gmail.com
Website:
https://multispectraconsultants.com
Abstract
The
charge of nihilism in relation to emptiness is a charge that is all
too familiar to the Madhyamika. This paper attempts to explain and
extrapolate Burton’s nihilist objection to Madhyamaka Buddhist
thought and dispel it with primary recourse to original writings by
Nagarjuna and subsequent commentators such as Candrakirti. I examine
how the Madhyamika can avoid the trappings of nihilism whilst
simultaneously arguing that conventional phenomena (persons and
entities) are empty of intrinsic existence or essence, thus
illustrating how Madhyamaka philosophy works as a cogent Middle Way
between nihilism and eternalism.
To
this end, I have split the paper into four distinct but interrelated
sections, with each one laying the groundwork for the next and
building upon the last. The four topic areas subsumed under our main
endeavour to refute Burton’s claim of nihilism are; I: Emptiness
and its Foundations, II: Emptiness and Nihilism, III: The Madhyamika
Method and IV: Emptiness, the Noble Truths and the Two-Truth
Position. Each section attempts to deal with the subtleties of both
Madhyamaka thought and Burton’s criticisms with the eventual goal
being vindication of Nagarjuna’s school of Buddhism in virtue of
the no-view goal that characterises enlightenment: the Madhyamika
aims to relinquish all views, not engage in metaphysical jostling to
score points. I conclude by arguing that Burton’s criticisms are
incorrect because he has misunderstood or misconstrued the
conventional Madhyamika position by attacking a metaphysic that is of
no great importance to the wider Madhyamaka project and by
misunderstanding precisely what emptiness is by reifying it as some
sort of obscure substratum.
Introduction
Does
emptiness as expounded by Madhyamaka philosophy necessitate nihilism?
There is a consistent line of objections that argue that Nagarjuna
and his commentators fall into nihilism unwittingly via their
arguments for the emptiness of entities, and in order to begin to
answer this important question, we will first need to undertake some
groundwork to contextualise Nagarjuna’s philosophy. Nagarjuna saw
his philosophy as a back-to-basics ‘original Buddhist’ response
to the Abhidharmika projects that dominated the Buddhist landscape
when he lived and wrote, and in Section I, I will further develop the
thesis that Nagarjuna was trying to assert emptiness as a necessary
truth implicit within the Buddha’s original teachings. We shall see
that his reasons for doing this are not at all obscure, but are, he
thinks, rooted in the Buddhist doctrines of dependent origination
(interdependence) and impermanence (change). Section II will see us
assess the implications of emptiness for phenomena, objects and
persons: we lay the foundations to begin to answer what I consider to
be the most dogged refutation facing the Madhyamika: the charge of
nihilism. Specifically, we will look to David Burton’s allegations
of nihilism and examine how they impact Madhyamaka philosophy.
Following on from this, Section III will present an examination of
the Madhyamika method; the means by which the Madhyamika argues for
emptiness. This will allow us to assess the nihilistic charges made
in Section II and give us some insight into how Nagarjuna and
subsequent adherents use a negative method to convince the objector
to relinquish their stance. I aim to argue that Madhyamaka philosophy
at large is doctrineless and uses the negative method to achieve a
total relinquishing of views in order to negate attachment and
subsequently remove suffering. Section IV will attempt to tie
emptiness, the Four Noble Truths and the Two-Truth method together by
highlighting exactly how the Madhyamika places emptiness at the heart
of the Noble Truths and how the conventional viewpoint differs from,
impacts upon and to some degree leads one to the ultimate viewpoint.
We will discuss why this is significant and how correctly realising
the conventional truth in order to progress toward the ultimate truth
can aid the Madhyamika avoid charges of nihilism. My main text for
achieving these aims will be the Garfield (1995) translation of the
Mulamadhyamakakarika, Nagarjuna’s seminal text. Our principal
chapters for this endeavour will be Chapters XVIII and XXIV
(Examination of Self and Entities; Examination of the Four Noble
Truths), as I feel that out of the entire work, these chapters are
pivotal if we wish to refute the charges of nihilism that we find
ourselves presented with. However, in order to appreciate the
background within which Nagarjuna was writing and developing his
thought, I will firstly spend some time outlining the Buddha’s
teaching of selflessness according to the Mahavagga and
Kaccayanagotta Sutta – this can, I hope, provide the stepping stone
we require to place Nagarjuna’s philosophy in some sort of context.
The end product of this endeavour will be, I hope, an exposition and
defence of Nagarjuna’s position regarding emptiness of phenomena
and persons, and so by extension, a rebuttal of Burton’s nihilism
objection.
I:
Emptiness and its Foundations
Nagarjuna’s
formulation (it is misleading to refer to it as a ‘doctrine’, as
we shall see later) of ‘emptiness’ (shunyata) is not explicitly
synonymous with the Buddha’s teaching of selflessness (anatman),
but is an extension of selflessness in that it argues that essence is
lacking from all phenomena. This complements the early Buddhist
teaching that experienced phenomena do not possess any associations
of ‘I’ or ‘mine’ and thus should not be clung to. Nagarjuna’s
project was to argue that all entities are without essence in any
form – a progression that he thought was merely consequent to the
Buddha’s original teachings regarding dependent origination and the
lack of essential selves in humans: put like this, the entire
endeavour seems utterly uncontroversial. However, Nagarjuna’s views
on essentialism were in stark contrast to the Abhidharmika views of
the time, and I believe that this was mostly down to his conviction
that the Buddha himself had implicitly refuted the notion of
essentialism in any meaningful sense. With this in mind, it is
worthwhile for us to examine how the Buddha formulated his own view
of selflessness before we determine how and why Nagarjuna wanted to
take it a step further and apply emptiness to persons and phenomena.
Firstly,
it is useful for us to note exactly what the Buddha was rallying
against, and this was, not to put too fine a point on it, the concept
of atman present in the Hindu Vedas. The atman points to an essential
self that sits outside of space and time. It is simple, unitary,
persistent and unchanging. It is ‘the innermost reality of the
individual, the subtle essence’ (Lipner, 2010: p53). The problem
here for the Buddha (and later for Nagarjuna) is the implication of
an eternal or unchanging essential self. Buddhism is a philosophy and
religion built entirely on the basis of life as a continual karmic
flux of causally conditioned phenomena governed by dependent
origination and, more importantly, the maxim in the Fourth Noble
Truth that there is an end to suffering: the Buddha would struggle to
claim that humans have an essential self that is born ignorant and
into suffering and yet despite this essential nature, can somehow
change to become enlightened and end suffering – after all, if
something is, for example, essentially red, how can we say that we
can change this nature to make the thing essentially blue?
It
is precisely this elaboration on the Buddha’s position that the
Madhyamaka school founded by Nagarjuna propagates: the very fact that
the atman is essential means that it is necessarily unchanging and
indeed unchangeable. In turn, this means that the presence of an
essential self makes accounting for the inner change that the Buddha
propagated as the means to reach enlightenment (and subsequently end
suffering) very difficult indeed – how can we change the
unchangeable? In virtue of this apparent contradiction, any concept
of a permanent, essential self must be eschewed. This is not to say
that there is a permanent self or ego of some description that can be
somehow quashed or removed via praxis. Nor does it mean that there is
a permanent self and it is just easier or better for Buddhist praxis
if the practitioner simply does not speak of it: Nagarjuna does not
identify a concrete, existent essential self whatsoever – instead,
he argues that all phenomena are empty of essence or self-existence.
To
understand why this is the case, some perspective on both the
Buddha’s position (and Nagarjuna’s subsequent position) can be
found in the Simile of the Snake. Here, the Buddha gives a list of
associations with which it is incorrect to identify a permanent,
unchanging self. This wrong-view includes ‘Look[ing] on what [one]
has seen, heard, sensed, known, experienced, pursued and pondered in
[one’s] mind as [one’s own]’(Gethin, 2008: p162), or in other
words, reconciling any aspect of subjective human experience as
representative – either in whole or in part – of the self. This
maxim is important because within the Buddhist paradigm (we cannot
lose sight of the fact that Nagarjuna was a religious writer who was
primarily concerned with soteriology), any I-notion (me, mine) is
both a symptom of and a source of bondage to suffering (duhkha)
through desire and attachment as described in the First Noble Truth:
‘This,
O Bhikkhus, is the Noble Truth of Suffering: Birth is suffering;
decay is suffering; illness is suffering; death is suffering.
Presence of objects we hate, is suffering; Separation from objects we
love, is suffering; not to obtain what we desire, is suffering.
Briefly, the fivefold clinging to existence is suffering.’
(Mahavagga [of the Vinaya], 6: 19-20)
In
addition to the Buddha’s position regarding the non-existence of an
essential self, both he and Nagarjuna think that clinging to an ‘I’
in any substantial form is to propagate one’s own suffering
indirectly. Surprisingly, the reasoning behind this counter-intuitive
claim is actually relatively simple. Whilst Buddhism does not deny
that there are things in life that we experience as pleasurable –
indeed, the Mahavagga has already mentioned that there are objects
that ‘we love’ in existence – ultimately, these pleasurable
experiences all inevitably lead to suffering. How? Well, it is
basically down to misperception: we enjoy something because we find
it pleasurable (insofar as it makes us fleetingly happy) and we
subsequently cultivate attachment to the pleasure, and then
(erroneously) to the object. Owing to our attachment to this pleasure
and the object of pleasure, we then try to replicate and reproduce
this pleasure: pleasure which we have already said is necessarily
fleeting and impermanent. Conventional realisation that this pleasure
is impermanent (we know that eating a cake will not usually instil a
permanent, deep happiness in us, for example) leads us back to the
beginning of the circle: we grasp at this attachment to pleasure,
gain pleasure temporarily and then experience varying degrees of
anguish until we can procure this pleasure again (paraphrased from
H.H. The Dalai Lama, 2000: pp50-51).
How
this relates to the self and I-notions may not be clear to the
non-Buddhist, but the logic goes along the following lines: the
common denominators in all of this are the subject of experience and
the object of pleasure; the reified essential self to which all of
these pleasurable experiences (and painful experiences) occur, and
the reified ‘pleasurable’ inanimate object. Attaching substantial
existence to the self and worrying about satisfying desires of the
‘I’ that we reify is a root cause of our suffering. To put it
simply, once we fully realise that the self and the ‘I’ that we
identify with is nothing more than a misperception – a collection
of aggregates subject to dependent origination rather than one
simple, unified essential entity that we ‘are’ – we realise the
futility in attaching value to the satisfaction of desires that we
think stem from this permanent self. Similarly, the object that we
perceive as pleasurable is also mistakenly reified – it has no
essential part that makes it pleasurable. With this in mind, the aim
of the Buddhist path is to both remove attachment to objects and
fleeting feelings such as pleasure, and to remove attachment to this
notion of a substantial, essential ‘I’. Success will break the
cycle and rid us of the erroneous perception that entities can exist
independently outside of ever-changing interrelated contexts.
With
this said, it is important to note that Nagarjuna does not deny that
we perceive a conventional ‘I’. It would be silly to say that we
do not feel a sense of something that it is to be ‘us’. For
Nagarjuna, though, this is merely due to myriad dependently-arisen
phenomena being experienced through the dependently-arisen skandhas
(aggregates of personhood: form; sensation; perception; volition;
consciousness). There is nothing about our experience that
necessitates there being an essential self – it is possible for us
to experience without there being an unchanging subject doing the
experiencing. It is the Madhyamika view that any notion of essence
should be jettisoned on account of both its inaccuracy as an
ontological claim (where, upon analysis, can we find our essential
self?) and its uselessness as a moral starting point for Buddhist
praxis (how can we reach enlightenment via praxis if change is
impossible owing to our essence?): the self that we identify and
reify naturally – the conventional I – is empty of essence.
It
can be argued that Nagarjuna’s denial of essential selfhood and
focus on the primacy of dependent origination stems from teachings
attributed to the Buddha himself and were merely reassertions and
slight elaborations on the Buddha’s own words: I certainly think
that this is how Nagarjuna saw his endeavours in the
Mulamadhyamakakarika. We can see how this might be the case if we
consider the Kaccayanagotta-sutta:
‘By
and large, Kaccayana, this world is supported by (takes as its
object) a polarity, that of existence & non-existence. But when
one sees the origination of the world as it actually is with right
discernment, 'non-existence' with reference to the world does not
occur to one. When one sees the cessation of the world as it actually
is with rightdiscernment, 'existence' with reference to the world
does not occur to one... ...‘Everything exists': That is one
extreme. 'Everything doesn't exist': That is a second extreme.
Avoiding these two extremes, the Tathagata teaches the Dhamma via the
middle...’ (Thanissaro Bikkhu, 1997).
This
passage is profoundly relevant to Nagarjuna’s project – the sutta
specifies that holding that everything exists is an extreme point of
view, and holding that nothing exists is the flipside of the same
coin: both are incorrect, hard-line positions. Subsequently, the wise
practitioner approaches from the middle (Madhyamaka does, after all,
translate as ‘Middle Way’) and does not commit to either
essentialism or nihilism. If we apply this principle to the problem
of selfhood, then Nagarjuna does not want to completely affirm nor
completely deny that there is a self of some description: we have
already seen that he does not deny the conventional ‘I’ (the
feeling of self that is imminent to us all) as long as it is empty of
essence – he only denies the essential ‘I’ that we reify. There
are reasons for this disdain toward essence: Nagarjuna’s
contemporaries were the Abhidharmika theorists that posited dharmas:
necessarily existent, basic elements that account for all mental and
physical phenomena, and so by extension manifest as part of the thing
we mistakenly call ‘self’ (Bartley, 2011: p30). The
Sarvastivadins wanted to use dharmas to explain persistent
characteristics in persons and objects, however, their account of
dharmas is lacking in terms of explaining precisely what they are and
how they work, and fraught with difficulties such as incoherence
about how they interact with each other and how (or why) there are
‘two-worlds’ (Donnelly, 2013: pp74-76).
That
the Abhidharmikas posited unconditioned essential features of reality
at all is too far a step away from the Buddha’s teachings according
to Nagarjuna: we have seen above that the Buddha specifically warned
against the position that everything exists – for Nagarjuna,
dharmas necessarily entail this position owing to their having
essence and their timeless existence in an unconditioned realm.
Further to this, Nagarjuna thinks that under the Sarvastivadin
account, dharmas are necessarily detached from dependent origination
(as they are unconditioned). It could be claimed that this does not
make much practical difference as they reside in an unconditioned
realm and migrate to the conditioned realm only to manifest
experiential phenomena. They then do this as part of conditioned
dependent origination in our conventional sphere of experience, and
so whilst they are distinct from dependent origination in one realm,
they are very much a part of it within this realm. However, I think
that this position is surely countered by Nagarjuna in the opening
verse of the Mulamadhyamakakarika when he states that nothing can
arise from itself, from something else, from both itself and
something else, or from no cause whatsoever in any realm
(Mulamadhyamakakarika I:1).
Within
this context, Nagarjuna is responding to the idea that a dharma can
reside timelessly as an unchanging, un-arisen entity in an
unconditioned realm: if a dharma is self-existent and unconditioned,
then it cannot have caused itself as this would indeed be a cause and
condition and timeless, eternal things cannot be caused or
conditioned! Similarly, it cannot have been caused by something else,
as this too is a cause and condition. Furthermore, it makes no sense
to say that something has been caused from nothing, as this is to
make a mockery of what we understand by ‘cause’. The conclusion
that we are left with as a result is either the absurdity that the
dharmas can still inexplicably fit within this framework, or the more
sensible position that they simply do not: they are empty of essence
and they too must be subject to dependent origination.
Nagarjuna
challenged the Sarvastivadin account of dharmas on the basis that all
phenomena are empty of essence and subject to dependent origination:
this does run contrary to the Abhidharmika stance which sees timeless
dharmas migrate from an unconditioned realm, and as such it is clear
to me that the Sarvastivadins held dharmas as eternal in at least
some sense. As a result, I feel that Nagarjuna challenged them both
ontologically and epistemically even if he did not directly say so:
we cannot categorise empty phenomena as eternal or timeless as this
would be to separate them necessarily from dependent origination, and
so the nature of dharmas is surely left open to question via
Nagarjuna’s method even if their existence (in a broad sense) is
not questioned.
We
have seen in this section how Nagarjuna formulated his doctrine of
emptiness as a logical step forward from the teachings of the Buddha.
We needed to look only to the Kaccayanagotta Sutta and the Mahavagga
to see the bases that Nagarjuna was working from: the Buddha himself
warned against taking up either an essentialist or nihilist position
in no uncertain terms, and Nagarjuna thought that if essentialism was
true, then there was no chance of change – if there was no chance
of change, then there was no option of liberation. That the
Abhidharmika schools (specifically the Sarvastivadins) pondered
essential qualities in any sense at all was a direct contravention of
the Buddha’s original teachings for Nagarjuna, who quite literally
saw essentialism as being a phenomenal anchor within the karmic flux;
a starting point or base where there ought not to be one.
Subsequently, we saw all concepts around essence shunned – be it in
persons or phenomena – by virtue of the conflict with original
Buddhist doctrine.
II:
Emptiness and Nihilism
In
the last section, we saw how Nagarjuna came to the conclusion that
essentialism necessarily contradicted the Buddha’s own teachings in
the Kaccayanagotta Sutta, and why he thought that to posit
essentialism in any description was to exclude dependent origination
– a key Buddhist doctrine – from some aspect of reality. For
Nagarjuna, there is nothing controversial in his assertion that
persons are empty of essence and entirely subject to dependent
origination just like any other existent phenomenon. However, it does
seem counter-intuitive for the non-Buddhist reader to say that we
have no ‘self’, ‘I’ or ‘me’, especially given that vast
swathes of the population seem to speak indiscriminately of the
‘soul’ or the ‘real me’. Is to deny the presence of an
essential self then to deny the existence of persons in any
recognisable fashion?
The
largest criticism that the Madhyamika continually has to face is that
of nihilism. David Burton contends that Nagarjuna’s philosophy
necessarily entails nihilism whether he intended to or not: the
emptiness of entities – be they persons or objects – must entail
the non-existence of entities (Burton, 1999: p90). In other words, if
persons are empty then it must be the case, according to Burton, that
persons do not exist, and Nagarjuna has committed to nihilism. A
portion of the debate here once again lies with dharmas and how they
exist and operate. In order to understand this, we need to recognise
that Burton thinks that the Abhidharmikas had it right, or in any
case, were more correct than Nagarjuna, and is tackling the issue of
selfhood from ‘the other side’, as it were. Whilst still adhering
to the Buddha’s teaching of no-self, the Abhidharmika (and,
presumably, Burton) does not accept that the person is empty in the
broad sense given that the person is constituted of dharmas that
necessarily have essences – entities can, on this view, have
determinate individual essences and still be subject to dependent
origination. If persons and entities are empty of essence, then
Burton contends that the person is reduced to mere concept and cannot
exist even conventionally. In other words, there must be something
unconditioned that provides the basis of construction for the
conditioned – we have seen how in the Abhidharma doctrines this is
provided by the dharmas. It is a familiar line in Western analytic
philosophy: it is not often that somebody will willingly commit to an
infinite regress of causes. The philosopher generally aims to
conceive of the grounding ground, or the first cause. It is, however,
less of a concern in traditional Buddhist soteriology and philosophy
where everything is famously explained in a circular fashion. The
Buddha himself identified the ‘twelve links’ – a circular
account of every possible experiential mental and physical phenomena:
ignorance; volition; consciousness; name and form; faculties and
objects; contact; sensation; craving; attachment; becoming; birth;
old age and death (Gethin, 2008: pp210-213). With this in mind, it is
easy to see how Burton arrives at this conclusion: as we said in the
previous section, Nagarjuna has rejected that anything can exist
independently of anything else in the very first verse of the
Mulamadhyamakakarika (and then spent the rest of his treatise
developing this notion). Burton aims to show that Nagarjuna must
necessarily commit to nihilism via a sort of misplaced idealism. We
will see how he reaches this conclusion, and how I intend to
demonstrate that his arguments might be incorrect.
As
Burton is approaching this issue from the Abhidharmika position, it
is important that we recognise what this position entails. In the
first section, we saw Nagarjuna’s attitude to dharmas, and at this
point it is prudent to go a little more in depth as to the
Abhidharmika formulation of dharmas. As we have already seen in
Section I, dharmas are the foundational components of the world; they
are irreducible to any parts and so are in this sense basic and have
an own-nature or essence that distinguishes each type of dharma from
the other types of dharma (seventy-five types in all)( Burton, 2001:
pp90-91). Burton specifies that according to the Vaibhaṣika
Abhidharma, there are four categories of conditioned (samskrita)
dharmas (form; consciousness; consciousness-factors;
non-consciousness conditioned factors) and only one category of
unconditioned dharmas (asamskrita): the seventy-five types of dharma
fall into one of these categories (Burton, 2001: p91).
The
conditioned dharmas are, as the name suggests, wholly subject to
dependent origination in that they have the characteristics of birth,
impermanence and decay, but pointing this out is not a rebuttal of
Nagarjuna’s point in any real terms and seems to me to be mere
assertion rather than argument. Burton appears to be simply stating
that the Abhidharma gives an account of how dharmas with essences can
work within a Buddhist paradigm. He is right – it does. However,
Nagarjuna is not saying that the Abhidharma does not offer an account
of how dharmas can work within the Buddhist paradigm; he is saying
that the account itself is incorrect in virtue of its essentialism.
Such a stance, claims Burton, means that at the very least –
nihilism notwithstanding – Nagarjuna must commit to the position
that there are no unconditioned dharmas. I think that this is also
true. However, I have already argued in Section I that Nagarjuna’s
method necessarily leaves precisely how dharmas exist and operate
open to question without seeking to make any further assertions about
them. Nagarjuna’s endeavour is, as I see it, a doctrineless
philosophy concerned with illustrating the absurdity of essentialism
rather than pushing an alternative doctrine to be clung to and
propagated, and so I am not convinced that this line of attack is a
comprehensive, convincing rebuttal of any sort.
As
a consequence of Burton’s interest in Nagarjuna’s formulation of
emptiness (and his own project of refuting it), Burton predictably
pays particular attention to chapter XVIII of the
Mulamadhyamakakarika (Examination of the Self and Entities). This is
perhaps Nagarjuna’s seminal elaboration upon selfhood, entities and
their emptiness. Here, Burton appears to categorise Nagarjuna as some
sort of idealist (temporarily, at least) by specifically arguing that
the whole of chapter XVIII could be an exercise in establishing the
mind-dependence of entities, concepts and persons (Burton, 2001:
p101). This would mean that Nagarjuna thinks that objects and
entities do exist, but that their existence is as conceptual
constructions of the mind rather than actual concrete entities
independent of the mind. The unintended outcome of this idealist
position is, according to Burton, nihilism: if all entities are empty
of essence and thus conceptually constructed, then there can be –
as we have seen in Nagarjuna’s objections to unconditioned dharmas
– no unconditioned/unconstructed bases out of which the conditioned
and constructed entities can be built (Burton, 2001: p109). If this
is the case, then – according to Burton –not only are we falling
into nihilism regarding persons and entities, but it also follows
that it is pointless to speak of discovering the ultimate truth or of
enlightenment: if the Four Noble Truths are mere conceptual
constructions with no inherent reality, then what is the function in
accepting them? They are relegated to figments of our imagination.
Similarly, if there is no substantial existence behind a person, what
is it to change our habits and reach enlightenment?
However,
I think that Burton has missed a trick here. If we analyse chapter
XVIII of the Mulamadhyamakakarika not as a standalone representation
of the entire Madhyamaka philosophy, but in context with the rest of
the treatise (particularly chapters XXIV and XXVII), we can see for
ourselves what Nagarjuna thought and possibly reach a different
conclusion. Firstly, though, we will look at chapter XVIII on its own
merit. This chapter aims to argue that entities arise only in a
context of innumerate causes and conditions because they lack
inherent essential existence. To put it slightly differently,
emptiness provides the very basis needed for entities to arise,
change, decay, and so on. Is this to fall prey to the very infinite
regress that Burton seeks to avoid? In the very first verse,
Nagarjuna writes:
‘If
the self were the aggregates,
It
would have arising and ceasing (as properties).
If
it were different from the aggregates,
It
would not have the characteristics of the aggregates.’
(Mulamadhyamakakarika, XVIII:1)
At
first glance, this passage may seem contradictory: it appears as if
Nagarjuna is saying that the self is simultaneously equivalent to the
skandhas and not equivalent to the skandhas. However, when we
consider what we said in Section I – that Nagarjuna is disputing
the existence of a permanent self rather than a sense of self – the
passage is not as problematic. Jay Garfield argues that all Nagarjuna
is doing here is stating that the bases of Buddhist psychology are
empty: if we posit a permanent self that is identifiable with the
skandhas, then we must concede that our permanent, inherently
existent and essential self is in a constant state of flux, open to
change and always being conditioned by outside factors. Obviously, we
would be loathe to say this – how can the self be permanent in any
recognisable sense if it is always changing and arising/ceasing?
Similarly, if this posited self is distinct from the skandhas, then
the relationship between skandhas and person becomes arcane at best
and completely unknowable at worst. In any case, if the self was
entirely distinct from the skandhas, we would be put in the bizarre
position of claiming that whatever sense experience occurs to
whatever skandha is somehow distinct from what is happening to me as
a conventional person (Garfield, 1995: p246). How can we address this
problem? Well, Nagarjuna has an answer for this, too:
‘If
there were no self,
Where
would the self’s (properties) be?
From
the pacification of the self and what belongs to it.
One
abstains from grasping onto “I” and “mine”.’
(Mulamadhyamakakarika, XVIII: 2)
This
is crucially important. The last two lines of the karika outline
Nagarjuna ‘s solution to the problem of selfhood and its subsequent
attachments: if we stop trying to think of a substratum in which the
properties we associate with the self inhere, we simply see
attributes as causally-conditioned associations that merely exist
rather than exist in something. Only then do we break the cycle of
reification of both self and other entities: we saw in Section I that
both the Buddha and Nagarjuna think the reification of self and
entities propagate suffering, and in this passage, we can see
Nagarjuna hint at a conventional I – that is, the feeling of a
sense of I; one that does actually have properties. It is important
to note that neither I nor Nagarjuna are claiming that there is a
permanent self on a conventional level. When I speak of a
‘conventional I’, I am referring only to the sense of self that
is apparent and immediate to all of us who have not achieved
liberation. We must tread carefully with our use of ‘self’ here,
for as Candrakirti writes, ‘Not only does [the self] not constitute
the basis for ego-clinging on the ultimate level, it [the self] has
no existence even on the level of conventional reality’
(Madhyamakavatara, 122). He is not disputing that we have a sense of
I that is apprehended, but arguing that this does not constitute
anything that should be termed ‘self’: ‘self’ necessarily has
connotations of permanence and inherent existence.
Can
we reconcile the position of no-(essential) self and still speak
about a conventional ‘I’? Burton thinks not: as we have already
seen, he thinks that to speak of a person as empty (of essential
self) or as mere conventional conceptual designation (the perceived
conventional I) is to reduce both to mental constructs and deny their
reality, thus slipping into nihilism. Taken individually, it is easy
to see how Burton might argue that these karikas present a nihilistic
view. However, we will see that far from reaching into nihilism (or
eternalism, for that matter), Nagarjuna does indeed take the Middle
Way that Burton concludes cannot lead to anything but nihilism. I
hope to show in the next section that he achieves this without
slipping into the throes of nihilism at all.
III:
The Madhyamika Method
Perhaps
Nagarjuna’s apparent dichotomy in Mulamadhyamakakarika XVIII: 2 is
not as problematic as it first appears. It is widely acknowledged
that the Buddha graduated his teachings depending on the ability and
understanding of his students. Such a method makes perfect sense to
us in a modern context, too: when I began my philosophy degree, we
did not delve into the intricacies of modal logic in the first week.
Following this, the argument for the Madhyamika is that even if it
were possible to merely communicate the realisation of emptiness
directly as a doctrine (we have already stated that viewing emptiness
as a doctrine is inaccurate, and it would also vastly understate –
neglect, even – the experiential and meditative aspect vital to
this realisation), the novice would not be equipped to grasp the full
gravitas of the teaching.
As
such, the realisation of emptiness must be guided through several
stages, beginning with the coarse and crudest type of rejection of
essentialism, and ending in the subtlest (Lobsang Gyatso, 2001:
pp52-53). To visualise how this might work, think of crossing a river
on a raft (a popular Buddhist metaphor): the raft is useful to us
only for as long as it takes us to complete our journey across the
river. From then, it is pointless to carry the raft with us, and so
the wise among us discard it.
Furthermore,
it can be said that the Madhyamika has no doctrine. In the
Prasannapada, Candrakirti writes that the Madhyamika ‘pursues his
own thesis only until the adversary gives up his’, and this
recurring sentiment is indicative of why I think that positing the
Madhyamika conception of emptiness as a doctrine in its own right is
inaccurate (Prasannapada, 19). Is it sensible to say that Nagarjuna
therefore wants to eventually refute doctrinal Buddhism rather than
redefine or add to it? This would fit with his wider project of
pushing the realisation of emptiness as the key to liberation: if the
doctrines that the Buddhist practitioner is adhering to are wrong,
then liberation will not be accessible or achieved. The only concern
of the Madhyamika, then, is realisation of emptiness and not
developing or critiquing metaphysical bases for the experienced world
outside of this pursuit. If we bear this in mind, we look back on
Nagarjuna’s critique of the Abhidharma in a different light: he is
not refuting their metaphysical perspective in favour of replacing it
with his own metaphysic per se, but rather refuting the Abhidharma
metaphysics in order to propagate a ‘no-view about reality’
(Nayak, 2001: p15).
Depending
on our stance regarding this explanation of Buddhist methodology as a
whole (and Madhyamika methodology specifically), we can either accept
that talk around a mundane, conventional I is permitted as a mere
stopgap on the greater path, or we can, as Burton presumably does,
rubbish it as an incongruence that confuses the Madhyamika position.
In my opinion, Burton makes a fatal error by confusing Madhyamaka
refutations of Abhidharmika positive assertions as doctrines in
themselves, and whilst he claims to be sympathetic to Nagarjuna’s
project of whittling down doctrine until the realisation of
emptiness, I do not think that he has fully grasped either the
methodology or the real aim. The Madhyamika is characterised by their
lack of positive assertions about reality. Nagarjuna himself wrote:
‘The
victorious ones have said
That
emptiness is the relinquishing of all views.
For
whomever emptiness is a view,
That
one will accomplish nothing.’ (Mulamadhyamakakarika, XIII: 8)
Given
that Nagarjuna was concerned with propagating the ‘Middle Way’
between both eternalism and nihilism (everything exists versus
nothing exists) as per the Buddha’s own teachings in the
Kaccayanagotta Sutta, it appears to me that his attack against the
Abhidharma is concerned only with the idea that dharmas exist with a
permanent essence that can exist in the past, present and future, and
not against the existence of dharmas as a whole. To elaborate, his
enterprise simply has no need for dharmas insofar as the Madhyamika
is not concerned with making positive assertions or arguments for
metaphysical bases – dharmas do not concern Nagarjuna. For this
reason, it is true that Nagarjuna does not challenge their existence
explicitly or directly even if his method does leave their mode of
existence open to question. This being the case, then Nagarjuna is
emphatically not arguing that all entities are conceptually
constructed only in the mind, nor is he committing to the notion that
they exist in some other way – he simply advocates no view at all.
As we can see in the above karika, Nagarjuna wants the practitioner
to disseminate all views – that is to say that the Madhyamika
should hold nor make any positive claims about reality. In practical
terms, this stops any notion of formulating a Madhyamaka metaphysics
dead in its tracks, as there is no room for discourse on what does or
does not inherently exist. Nayak put it rather succinctly when he
said that ‘a Madhyamika thinker... has no metaphysical axe to
grind’ (Nayak, 2001: p18).
Consequently,
I think that Burton has missed the point somewhat and is actually
presenting a classic example of the very reification that the
Madhyamika seeks to destroy. Whilst he and other Buddhist
schools/scholars expend time and energy looking for a first cause to
ground all entities and persons, Nagarjuna is not at all concerned
with this reification: Nagarjuna is concerned only with reiterating
what he thinks is implicit within the Buddha’s original teachings
and providing a method by which we can reach enlightenment. The
Buddha himself said that he did not want his words to be a ground for
metaphysical debate or to be adhered to merely in virtue of some
arbitrarily assigned truth value (Thanissaro Bhikkhu, 2010). With
emptiness, Nagarjuna is sidestepping any metaphysical bickering by
arguing for the futility (and outright absurdity) of debating
metaphysical positions! Burton would, of course, likely respond that
emptiness is in and of itself a positive statement about the nature
of reality: we are, after all, arguing that other conceptions of
selfhood are incorrect in virtue of emptiness. This is again, I
argue, a misunderstanding: emptiness itself must necessarily be empty
of essence, lest the Madhyamika drift into contradiction and
undermine her entire project. For Nagarjuna, holding emptiness as
mere view is, as we have seen, incorrect: emptiness is not something
real to be uncovered or realised as ‘real’ in contradistinction
to ultimately unreal objects of conventional perception – we cannot
have a view of emptiness in virtue of its emptiness. After all,
‘Emptiness is the relinquishing of all views’.
With
all this in mind, I am inclined to ask whether our current debate
with Burton around Nagarjuna’s philosophy is somewhat misguided –
Burton is rallying against Nagarjuna on the grounds of the purely
metaphysical charge (dharmas, essence and ultimate grounds for
dependent origination) of nihilism. Whilst this is important for many
Western (and some Buddhist) philosophers, we have already seen that
the Buddha did not want there to be any metaphysical disagreements
surrounding his words (at least in the social context in which he
lived and spoke), only doctrines to be utilised for correct practice
that can be abandoned after use (remember the raft?). He remained
famously silent on the ‘big’ questions, seeing them as a
distraction from addressing the here and now. It should also be
obvious by now that the metaphysics are of minimal concern to
Nagarjuna, too. What is crucial is the recognition of emptiness of
everyday phenomena in order to further Buddhist praxis and to reach
enlightenment, and this sits squarely within the paradigm first
outlined by the Buddha. It then follows that Nagarjuna accepts the
twelve links as a comprehensive account of all possible phenomena and
so is not at all worried about discovering or justifying a basic
entity or substratum from which everything else can emanate.
Just
as Burton is forming part of his critique of Nagarjuna on the basis
that Nagarjuna is either misinterpreting or misunderstanding
Abhidharma doctrine outside of its own context, I contend that he too
misinterprets and misrepresents Nagarjuna’s project in relation to
its context as a reiteration of the Buddha’s original teachings.
Whether or not we think this metaphysical niggling is important is of
course open to much more debate than my wordcount allows, but it is
important for us to note that Nagarjuna does not seek to create a
metaphysical framework as his end product – he actually seeks to
remove views that he sees as obstructing wisdom and truth rather than
instil new ones – these too would obscure wisdom and truth and
further remove us from liberation! To this end, Nagarjuna’s
eventual ‘deeper’ view of ‘neither self nor no-self’ can
begin to make more sense. It is simply the Middle Way between
selfhood and no-selfhood:
‘That
there is a self has been taught,
And
the doctrine of no-self,
By
the Buddhas, as well as the
Doctrine
of neither self nor nonself.’ (Mulamadhyamakakarika, XVIII: 6)
Can
this make sense? Well, surprisingly, maybe it can: we have already
said that the Madhyamika is not concerned with establishing a
metaphysical position as such, but with removing views. If we take
this as our central tenet, all the Madhyamika is really saying is
that clinging to either a position of self or a position of no-self
is still clinging to something. Neither a conception of self nor a
conception of no-self actually aligns with an existent entity from
the ultimate viewpoint. Ergo, by not subscribing to either, the
Madhyamika is staying true to the same Middle Way that he has been
concerned with sticking to all along – the Middle Way avoids
metaphysical extremes and recognises the uncharacterisable nature
(for lack of a better word) of existence.
I
hope that I have illustrated how the method of the Madhyamika affects
their philosophy: we see metaphysical extremes discussed, negated and
abandoned in favour of a Middle Way that aims to make no positive
metaphysical assertions about the nature of reality or the entities
that appear to exist within it. Nagarjuna appears to have thought
that metaphysical attacks against his philosophy were doomed to
failure instantly, owing to the fact that they posit a metaphysic in
the first place! As such, Burton’s criticisms of emptiness and its
formulation would be repudiated by the Madhyamika as a shining
example of precisely the sort of clinging that the Madhyamika aims to
subdue and remove via their negative method. In the next section, I
will attempt to tie this together by demonstrating how and why
Nagarjuna placed emptiness at the very heart of Buddhist praxis in
relation to the central tenets of the entire Buddhist worldview in
all of its variations – the Four Noble Truths.
IV:
Emptiness, the Noble Truths and the Two-Truth Position
We
now move forward to chapter XXIV of the Mulamadhyamakakarika – The
Examination of the Four Noble Truths. This is vital in
contextualising the Madhyamaka school’s philosophy and
consolidating the rest of the Mulamadhyamakakarika – Jay Garfield
argues (correctly, in my view) that this chapter is really about the
nature of emptiness itself, its relation to our conventional reality,
and the construction of a negative argument refuting nihilistic
charges (Garfield, 1995: p 293). I will extrapolate Nagarjuna’s
means to achieve this and show how Nagarjuna provides a convincing
negative argument against nihilism.
It
is with regard to the Noble Truths that we can really see why
Nagarjuna and his subsequent commentators were so keen to avoid
metaphysical jousting, but it is also here that Burton’s argument
can appear to gather some veracity by proxy. As we saw in the prior
sections, Burton contends that if all phenomena are given reality
only in virtue of conceptual constructs and not in virtue of
essential existence of some type, then it follows that nothing exists
objectively and the Madhyamika slips into nihilism. This is not a new
criticism, and in karikas 1 and 2 of chapter XXIV, Nagarjuna’s
opponent claims that if everything is empty, then the Four Noble
Truths cannot exist:
‘If
all of this is empty,
Neither
arising, nor ceasing,
Then
for you it follows that
The
Four Noble Truths do not exist.
If
the Four Noble Truths do not exist,
Then
knowledge, abandonment,
Meditation,
and manifestation
Will
be completely impossible.’ (Mulamadhyamakakarika, XXIV: 1-2)
We
can see in this objection where Burton might have got his inspiration
– the positions of the objector and of Burton are close. Though not
identical in content, they both have nihilism as their conclusion.
Whereas Burton is primarily concerned with the existence of concrete
entities such as persons, trees and so on, this objector is taking
the same line of attack to try and refute Nagarjuna at the very core
of his Buddhist practice: simply put, if the objector can prove that
Nagarjuna’s position contradicts or somehow precludes the Noble
Truths, then there is no discussion to be had – he simply cannot
hold his position and still claim to be a Buddhist.
As
such, I feel that this section constitutes the absolute crux of
Nagarjuna’s project. In earlier sections I have examined how the
Madhyamika approach might impact everyday understanding of phenomena:
empty persons, existence of entities and so on. I also argued that
such metaphysical niggling was really something of a by-the-by for
both Nagarjuna and the long line of commentators in his wake:
Nagarjuna is only concerned with providing a method with which to
escape suffering because of his Buddhist beliefs and his acceptance
of the Four Noble Truths. So how can Nagarjuna and the Madhyamika
respond to the charges made against them by the objector?
The
Madhyamika defence hinges on the objector’s misunderstanding of
emptiness and a misunderstanding of the Two-Truth position. As we
have already stated elsewhere in this paper, emptiness is not the
‘true essence’ of existence; such reification of emptiness is as
erroneous as the reification of any other concept or entity. The
objector is, Nagarjuna holds, foisting their own misunderstanding of
emptiness onto Nagarjuna – putting words in his mouth, if you will:
‘We
say that this understanding of yours
Of
emptiness and the purpose of emptiness
And
of the significance of emptiness is incorrect.
As
a consequence you are harmed by it.
The
Buddha’s teaching of the Dharma
Is
based on two truths:
A
truth of worldly convention
And
an ultimate truth.’ (Mulamadhyamakakarika, XXIV: 7-8)
The
Two-Truth position (conventional; ultimate) is primary here and
warrants some exposition. Garfield argues that the Two-Truths have a
unity between them. That is to say, that both are ‘true’ to equal
degrees insofar as one is not presented as an untruth in relation to
the other, and one is not sublated by the other. What is true for
Garfield, though, is that the ultimate truth takes precedence for the
Buddhist soteriological ends, but this is not to place one over and
above the other (Garfield, 1995: p297). Initially, it seems as though
Garfield’s reading may present a problem, however; I cannot help
but wonder that if one truth is given precedence on soteriological
grounds (realisation of the ultimate as a release from suffering),
then surely it is simply given precedence ipso facto?
Khensur
Rinpoche writes that conventional truths include all of the perceived
phenomena that we see around us, whilst ultimate truths are the
emptiness(es) of these phenomena from inherent existence (Khensur
Jampa Tegchock, 2012: p232). A superficial reading of this might
agree with Garfield’s reading that both truths are ‘true’ –
at least from their respective referential frames. It might, however,
jar with his argument that neither sublates the other: for the
unenlightened, conventional truths are indeed ‘true’, but
similarly, for the awakened, the ultimate truth is true seemingly at
the expense of the conventional – the ultimate truth for Khensur
Rinpoche trumps the conventional on at least some level because it
reveals the truth about how entities actually exist rather than how
they appear to exist (Khensur Jampa Tegchock, 2012: p232). Garfield –
correctly, in my view, given the eventual importance of relinquishing
views – rejects this reading of an appearance/reality distinction
as out of context with the rest of the text (Garfield, 1995, p297),
and stops just short of equating the Two-Truths with each other
completely, writing that ‘the understanding of ultimate truth is in
an important sense the understanding of the nature of the
conventional truth...’ (Garfield, 1995: p299). It is likely that
from the conventional viewpoint that Garfield and I both presumably
occupy, the ultimate truth and complete realisation of it is the
higher ideal – it is here that we see the relinquishing of views
that Nagarjuna earlier championed as the hallmark of the enlightened
Madhyamika. If we switch this around and ask if it is true that for
an enlightened being, their position of ultimate truth is still the
higher ideal, I think it is obvious that the answer has to be ‘yes’.
However, it is clear now what Garfield meant when he said that the
Two-Truths were equally weighted: although he came dangerously close
to wholly equating the two (erroneously), his initial thought that
they are too important to each other to rank in terms of ‘more
true’ or ‘less true’ is, I feel, correct. How can this be? Is
it as simple, then, as saying that the difference between the
Two-Truths is a shift in outlook and frame of reference? It seems to
me that there is an irrefutable contingency between the ultimate
truth and the conventional truth: we express – or at least try to
guide people towards realising – the ultimate truth through
writings such as the Mulamadhyamakakarika, and this means that the
ultimate truth is, in effect, being pursued through conventional
means – we are still grasping at views in order to attain a
different, progressive view in order to realise emptiness and remove
views. Indeed, we would struggle to conceive of any alternative means
of pursuit or communication! To relate this back to karikas 1 and 2
(of Mulamadhyamakakarika XXIV), the Madhyamika response is simply to
say that the Four Noble Truths are conventional truths: they exist
conventionally in that we can assess their truth in relation (to link
back to dependent origination) to the observable world that we
inhabit. As they are conventionally true, they are useful to us on
our quest to realise the ultimate truths. This is where the close
similarity but also significant differences between conventional
truth and ultimate truth are most applicable: Garfield thinks that to
realise conventional truths (interdependence, the Four Noble Truths
and so on) basically is to realise ultimate truth (emptiness), but
whilst I can agree to a very close correlation, it also seems obvious
to me that the two are not the same.
To
elaborate, I appeal to Khensur Rinpoche, who expresses this ever so
succinctly when he writes that ‘The fact that the two truths are
one nature does not mean that they are the same thing’ and
continues to argue that for two things to be ‘the same’ requires
that they be nominally identical: this would mean that they share the
precise same name and be the precise same thing (Khensur Jampa
Tegchock, 2012: p233). Obviously this is not the case: the
conventional truth might be incredibly closely connected to the
ultimate truth, but it is not the same: if it were the same, the two
ways of referring to it would be redundant. As a crude example (but
one that performs our task more than adequately), we can again borrow
a word or two from Khensur Ripoche: if a table is conventionally true
(insofar as we apprehend it, it has the characteristics that
consensus agrees a table should have and is subject to dependent
arising, decay and so on), then we can say ‘yes, there is a table’.
However, this conventional truth does nothing to speak of the table’s
emptiness – if we merely say ‘there is a table’, it is not
conveying anything about the emptiness of the table. Similarly,
speaking of the emptiness of the table is not identical with speaking
of the table qua table (Khensur Jampa Tegchock, 2012: pp236-237).
As
a result, we can say with some degree of confidence that whilst the
Two-Truths are not the same, they are incredibly closely related and
that conventional truths, when viewed from an ultimate perspective,
are false in one important sense – they are views. This need not be
a problem, though; we said earlier in the paper that Buddhist
teachings are graduated and we can see them as a raft to be utilised
to get past the river, but discarded once we traverse the difficult
terrain. I do not see why this cannot also be the case here; once the
enlightened mind has seen ultimate truth (emptiness), then the views
held at the conventional level can simply be dispersed.
How,
we may ask, does all this affect the Noble Truths? Well, we have seen
that the objection is simply false, for it is not the case that
emptiness necessitates that nothing exists: we have seen the
Madhyamika argue that things do exist, just not in the manner that
the unenlightened mind perceives them to. Similarly, we now know that
the Noble Truths are conventional truths to be used to reach the
ultimate position. Further, to hold that emptiness is false would be
to hold that dependent origination is false, as we said in Section I.
In this case, the Buddha’s teaching of the Noble Truths actually do
become problematic – if the objector is arguing that emptiness is
false, then they are, according to Nagarjuna, in effect stating that
nothing can change as dependent origination must too be false. We can
see how this argument is going to unfold – if dependent origination
is false and there is no arising, ceasing, change or development and
decay, then how can suffering arise? Such a position is necessarily a
contravention of the First Noble Truth (suffering exists) as well as
the Second Noble Truth (suffering has a cause) – how can we account
for the existence of suffering if it is not dependently arisen? If it
were to exist under its own power, then it must have an essence; this
in turn means that suffering cannot be changed or ended. This is of
pivotal importance: for suffering to have an essential existence
would preclude it from dependent origination and thus make it very
difficult for the Buddhist to account for the impact of the Buddhist
path – how do we change what is basic, immutable and thus
unchangeable? This issue is sidestepped completely, though, if we
realise that suffering (along with every other conventionally
existent phenomenon) is simply empty of essence.
For
Nagarjuna, the final nail in the coffin of the objector’s argument
is delivered with the realisation that the Fourth Noble Truth (the
Buddhist path to suffering’s cessation) can only be true in virtue
of emptiness because without emptiness, no change is possible for or
in any phenomenon at all. Nagarjuna has turned the objector’s own
argument against the objector to illustrate how – contrary to the
objection – nihilism is not the necessary conclusion of Madhyamaka
philosophy. Ironically, though, we can see that the objection itself
does spell trouble for the Noble Truths. Subsequently, it is not the
Madhyamika that is misguided, but the objector.
Conclusion
By
way of conclusion, we now return to our initial question – does
emptiness as expounded by Madhyamaka philosophy entail nihilism? We
have seen why Nagarjuna was keen to eschew any notion of selfhood for
all phenomena and entities as a means both to relieve suffering and
also to eventually end suffering. We also discussed how we must be
careful to avoid the reification of emptiness, as it would be very
easy for us to fall into the trap of holding emptiness to be a ‘true’
representation of some sort, or a substratum that is eternal and
independent of entities – this would not be nihilistic, but it
would be eternalistic, and for the Madhyamika, this is just as
undesirable an outcome. It must be the case, as mentioned earlier,
that emptiness is itself empty if the Madhyamika wants to make any
sense. This is to say that if we attempt to analyse emptiness – to
find it –we see nothing except a lack of inherent existence.
Emptiness is not a substance, entity or existent essence, but a lack
of all these things.
To
briefly demonstrate this, let us return to the table example. We can
disassemble a table in our minds to visualise of all its constituent
parts; legs, tabletop, screws et cetera. But if we tried to look for
the table’s emptiness, what would we find? We cannot strip down its
parts and discover some thing that emptiness is, but rather we find
that we cannot find anything except the table’s lack of essential,
inherent existence. The table is simply dependent – this is the
realisation of emptiness. This cannot be the same as nihilism: the
table still exists, for we are looking right at it!
As
a result, I simply cannot agree with Burton that emptiness leads to
nihilism. We have seen how Nagarjuna and his subsequent commentators
sought to refute essentialism not to push an agenda that says
‘nothing exists’, but rather ‘nothing inherently exists’ –
something markedly different. I have argued that the Madhyamika does
not – in accordance with traditional Buddhist teachings (the twelve
links) – require nor desire a causa sui. Consequently, Burton’s
appeal to an essential, necessary metaphysical grounding ground for
the subsequent dependent origination of all entities is misplaced and
entirely irrelevant to the Madhyamika thinker who is primarily
concerned with the ‘relinquishing of views’ to negate attachment
to entities for a soteriological ends. Following this line of
thought, the importance of emptiness to the Four Noble Truths has
been demonstrated in Section III, namely that change requires
emptiness and the Four Noble Truths all hinge on change – if there
is essence it is necessarily immutable and cannot be changed. If it
cannot be changed, how do we end suffering? Similarly, the Two-Truth
method has, I hope, been shown to provide the tools needed for the
Madhyamika to progress her thought from conventional to ultimate
without falling into any traps of nihilism or contradiction outlined
in this paper.
All
in all, I hope that I have gone some way to demonstrating the
coherence of Nagarjuna’s formulation of emptiness, the veracity of
the Madhyamika method, and why I do not believe that Nagarjuna’s
philosophy necessitates nihilism. I am convinced that Burton’s
objections are either irrelevant to the Madhyamika or
misrepresentative of the Madhyamaka position, and it is my sincere
hope that I have justified and vindicated my own position in this
paper.
Bibliography
Bartley,
C., 2011, An Introduction to Indian Philosophy. London: Continuum.
Burton,
D., 1999. Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna’s
Philosophy. Delhi: Motilal Barnasidass.
Candrakirti,
Madhyamakavatara, In Jamgön Mipham (Eds.), 2004. Introduction to the
Middle Way: Chandrakirti's Madhyamakavatara with Commentary. Boston:
Shambhala Publications Ltd.
Candrakirti,
Prasannapada, In Sprung, M. (Trans.), 1979. Lucid Expression of the
Middle Way: The Essential Chapters of Candrakirti Translated from the
Sanskrit. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.
Garfield,
J., 1995. The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way: Nagarjuna’s
Mulamadhyamakakarika. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gethin,
R., 2008. Sayings of the Buddha: New translations by Rupert Gethin
from the Pali Nikayas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jones,
R. H., 2010. Nagarjuna: Buddhism’s Most Important Philosopher. New
York: Jackson Square Books.
Lipner,
J., 2010. Hindus: their religious beliefs and practices. Oxon:
Routledge.
Lobsang
Gyatso & Woodhouse, G., 2001. Tsongkhapa’s Praise For Dependent
Relativity. Boston: Wisdom Publishing.
Khensur
Jampa Tegchock, 2012. Insight Into Emptiness. Boston: Wisdom
Publications.
Mahavagga
(of the Vinaya), 6: 19-20.
http://www.sacred-texts.com/bud/sbe13/sbe1312.htm [Last accessed:
03/05/2013]
Nayak,
G.C., 2001. Madhyamika shunyata: A Reappraisal. New Delhi: Indian
Council of Philosophical Research.
Tenzin
Gyatso, His Holiness The Fourteenth Dalai Lama of Tibet, 2000.
Ancient Wisdom, Modern World: Ethics for the New Millennium. London:
Abacus.
Thanissaro
Bikkhu, 1997. Kaccayanagotta Sutta, SN 12.15.
http://www.accesstoinsight.org/tipitaka/sn/sn12/sn12.015.than.html
[Last accessed: 03/05/2013] 36
Thanissaro
Bhikkhu, 2010. Wings to Awakening: Part I. Metta Valley Monastery:
California.
No comments:
Post a Comment